慶應義塾大学学術情報リポジトリ(KOARA)KeiO Associated Repository of Academic resources

慶應義塾大学学術情報リポジトリ(KOARA)

Home  »»  Listing item  »»  Detail

Detail

Item Type Article
ID
AN00150430-00000033-0069  
Preview
Image
thumbnail  
Caption  
Full text
AN00150430-00000033-0069.pdf
Type :application/pdf Download
Size :3.5 MB
Last updated :Aug 24, 2010
Downloads : 927

Total downloads since Aug 24, 2010 : 927
 
Release Date
 
Title
Title デイルタイと理念の歴史についての考察  
Kana ディルタイ ト リネン ノ レキシ ニ ツイテ ノ コウサツ  
Romanization Dhirutai to rinen no rekishi ni tsuite no kosatsu  
Other Title
Title An essay on Wilhelm Dilthey and the history of ideas  
Kana  
Romanization  
Creator
Name 西村, 皓  
Kana ニシムラ, ヒロシ  
Romanization Nishimura, Hiroshi  
Affiliation 慶應義塾大学  
Affiliation (Translated)  
Role  
Link  
Edition
 
Place
東京  
Publisher
Name 三田哲學會  
Kana ミタ テツガクカイ  
Romanization Mita tetsugakukai  
Date
Issued (from:yyyy) 1957  
Issued (to:yyyy)  
Created (yyyy-mm-dd)  
Updated (yyyy-mm-dd)  
Captured (yyyy-mm-dd)  
Physical description
 
Source Title
Name 哲學  
Name (Translated)  
Volume  
Issue 33  
Year 1957  
Month 3  
Start page 69  
End page 103  
ISSN
05632099  
ISBN
 
DOI
URI
JaLCDOI
NII Article ID
 
Ichushi ID
 
Other ID
 
Doctoral dissertation
Dissertation Number  
Date of granted  
Degree name  
Degree grantor  
Abstract
I shall not, in this essay, attempt to deal with Dilthey's accomplishments in the realm of pure philosophy. I shall here consider rather Dilthey's value as an historian of ideas. The unique structure of his mind, however, forbids a complete separation of his historical research from its philosophical origins. Dilthey defined the dominating impulse of his philosophical thought as the desire to comprehend human life in its own terms. Dilthey was profoundly impressed by the problems which his age had been set in the realm of state and society, and was, therefore, appreciative of the efforts of Comte and Mill. However, he imagined that any attempt to force the vast field of the humanities into the strait-jacket of the so-called scientific method was doomed to failure. He sought a more adequate approach to the complexities of the human world, and found it in history. His philosophical efforts to find the way into the domain of reality, to lay valid foundations insuring an objective knowledge of it - this urge was but the other side of his desire to penetrate the historical world more deeply. In such a manner did Dilthey become the historian of ideas, for a man to whom history and philosophy are but two different aspects of the same central approach will of necessity present history as the history of ideas. He will see ideas at the core of world history. To understand reality through history was, theretore, Dilthey's aim. History should be not only a revival of the past, as Ranke desired; it should be the means of understanding life. It would not be worthwhile to be an historian, if it were not also a way to understand the world. What in Kant and Herder had been the work of two full lifetimes, what Hegel had violently forced into the units of his dialectic, Dilthey in a strictly scientific manner, attempted to amalgamate. The relativities and the universally valid must be brought into deeper connection. The sympathetic understanding of all things past must become a force to form the future. Thus Dilthey appears as both philosopher and historian, as a worker immersed in the attempt to constitute the world of the mind in its own right, and as the discoverer of a new continent on the globus ihtellectualis. Dilthey does not try to explain the changes in history as a dialectic movement of concepts; he looks for deeper causes - the real evolution of man. Dilthey was bound to the heroic age of Germany not only by love and tradition; be found that in its poetry, philosophy, history, and educational viewpoint, a new metaphysics of life itself had emerged to which he could and did adhere. Dilthey rejected the form in which Schelling, Fichte, Hegel, and Schopenhauer manifested this idea, but he affirmed its content, because it contained his OWD belief, that life is a central point of meditation. Compared with Herder's or Hegel's grandiose visions or even with Rauk's story of the world, Dilthey's attempts lack unity and coherence. He had neither Herder's belief in humanity nor Hegel's faith in the progress of the consciousness of liberty, nor Comte's conviction of the triumph of science. He was a relativist. Universal history existed for him not as a problem to solve extensively, but only intensively.
 
Table of contents

 
Keyword
 
NDC
 
Note

 
Language
日本語  
Type of resource
text  
Genre
Journal Article  
Text version
publisher  
Related DOI
Access conditions

 
Last modified date
Dec 03, 2012 10:44:06  
Creation date
Aug 24, 2010 09:00:00  
Registerd by
mediacenter
 
History
Dec 3, 2012    フリーキーワード を変更
 
Index
/ Public / Faculty of Letters / Philosophy / 33 (195703)
 
Related to